Table of contents for Fundamentally wrong : how extremists are transforming the courts and the constitution / Cass R. Sunstein.

Bibliographic record and links to related information available from the Library of Congress catalog.

Note: Contents data are machine generated based on pre-publication provided by the publisher. Contents may have variations from the printed book or be incomplete or contain other coding.


Counter
Table of Contents
Preface
Introduction: The Constitution in Exile
Part I: The Great Divide
Chapter 1: Fundamentalists and Minimalists, Perfectionists and Majoritarians
Chapter 2: History's Dead Hand
Part II: The Great Divisions
Chapter 3: Is There a Right to Privacy?
Chapter 4: Who May Marry?
Chapter 5: Race and Affirmative Action
Chapter 6: National Security
Chapter 7: Minimalism At War
Chapter 8: Separation of Powers
Chapter 9: Guns, God, and Much More
Chapter 10: Fundamentals
Preface
Every day of every year, we Americans are freer because of our Constitution. If we're allowed to say what we like, worship as we choose, proceed without fear of the police, and even govern ourselves, we owe a large debt to our founding document. But our freedom is more fragile than it appears. The meaning of the Constitution is often disputed, and the disputes are often settled by the Supreme Court of the United States. The rights of Americans depend on what the Court says, and the Court doesn't always say what it said before.
It is customary to describe battles over the Constitution as pitting "liberals" against "conservatives," but this description is hopelessly inadequate. While ideology matters, different judges follow radically different approaches to constitutional law, and these approaches go well beyond ideology. My first goal in this book is to describe the four approaches that have long dominated constitutional debates, and to show how these approaches apply to the constitutional questions that trouble us today.
Two of them are minority positions, claiming distinguished historical pedigrees but few supporters on the current federal courts. I will argue for a third, which continues to have strong representation on the judiciary and in the nation as a whole. The fourth, which is ascendant, threatens both our democracy and our rights.
The first position is favored by many American liberals. We may call it perfectionism. Perfectionists want to make the Constitution the best that it can be. They follow the document's text but are entirely willing to understand that text in a way that reflects their own deepest beliefs about freedom of speech, equal protection of the laws, the power of the President, and other fundamental questions. Perfectionism played a major role in the liberal decisions of the Supreme Court under Chief Justice Earl Warren-the court that, among many other things, banned racial segregation in America; required a rule of one person, one vote; prohibited compulsory school prayer; and provided broad protection to political dissent. Many American liberals are willing to ask the Supreme Court to recognize or create new rights of many different kinds. When liberal perfectionists are committed, in principle, to a right, they often want the Supreme Court to say that that right is part of the Constitution.
The second position is majoritarianism. Majoritarians want to reduce the role of the Supreme Court in American government by allowing the democratic process to work its will. Unless the Constitution has been plainly violated, majoritarians believe, the courts should defer to the judgments of elected representatives. This commitment to bipartisan restraint would both permit affirmative action programs and allow states to forbid same-sex sodomy. Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., perhaps the greatest figure in the history of American law, was a majoritarian, and majoritarianism has recently attracted significant support among lawyers and law professors. Remarkably, however, it is hard to find a consistent majoritarian on today's Supreme Court.
The third position is minimalism. Minimalists are skeptical about general theories of interpretation; they want to proceed one step at a time. They are willing to nudge the law in one or another direction, but they refuse to promote a broad agenda and are skeptical of "movement judges" of any kind. They insist that the Constitution is not frozen in the past. But they are nervous about the exercise of judicial power, and they are skeptical of those who believe that the Supreme Court should be elaborating new rights and liberties lacking a clear foundation in our traditions and practices. Minimalists may be either conservative or liberal; their distinguishing feature is that they believe in narrow, incremental decisions, not broad rulings that the nation may later have cause to regret. Justice Felix Frankfurter was a distinguished minimalist; Justices Sandra Day O'Connor and Stephen Breyer are (mostly) minimalists; and I argue for minimalism in this book. .
The fourth position is fundamentalism. Fundamentalists believe that the Constitution must be interpreted according to the "original understanding"-it must be jnterpreted to mean exactly what it meant at the time it was ratified. If the Constitution did not originally ban the federal government from discriminating on the basis of race, then the federal government is permitted to discriminate on that basis. If the Constitution did not originally permit Congress to ban child labor, then Congress cannot ban child labor. If the Constitution did not originally give broad protection to political dissent, then courts cannot give broad protection to political dissent.
My second goal in this book is to explain what is wrong with the fundamentalist position.
As a constitutional creed, fundamentalism bears an obvious resemblance to religious fundamentalism. Religious fundamentalism usually represents an effort to restore the literal meaning of a sacred text. For fundamentalists, it is illegitimate to understand the words of those texts in a way that departs from the original meaning or that allows changes over time. "Strict construction" of the Constitution finds a parallel in literal interpretation of the Koran or the Bible. Some fundamentalists seem to approach the Constitution as if it were inspired directly by God. But since my topic is law, not religion, I do not mean to say anything about religious fundamentalism. It is in constitutional law that fundamentalism can be shown to be destructive and pernicious. Fundamentalism would make Americans much less free than they now are. It would constrict the right to free speech. It would eliminate the right of privacy. It might well allow states to establish official religions. It would do much more.
Fundamentalists often assert that theirs is the only legitimate approach to the Constitution. This is arrogant and wrong. Moreover, many prominent fundamentalists have not hesitated to betray their commitment to the original understanding when the historical evidence about that understanding points to results they dislike. Their willingness to do so suggests that some of the time, they are speaking for a partisan ideology rather than for law. In extreme cases, the role of ideology is transparent-as in the disgraceful attack on an independent judiciary during the 2005 effort to ask federal judges to reinsert the feeding tube of Terri Schiavo, a brain-damaged woman in Florida. We live in an era in which some prominent politicians are demanding that the courts interpret the Constitution to conform to the Republican party platform-and threatening judges with reprisal if they refuse to do as politicians want.
This effort should be rejected. My plea, in the end, is for minimalism-an approach to the Constitution that refuses to freeze the document in the eighteenth century, but that firmly recognizes the limited role of the federal judiciary and makes a large space for democratic self-government.
It is not at all pleasant to challenge, as wrong, dangerous, radical, and occasionally hypocritical, the many people of honor and good faith who have come to embrace fundamentalism. Fundamentalists are right to seek to cabin judicial power, and their democratic intuitions are a good starting point for constitutional law. But I hope to show that the most appealing goals of fundamentalism can be accomplished in much better ways-and that many of fundamentalism's goals are not appealing at all.
.

Library of Congress Subject Headings for this publication:

Political questions and judicial power -- United States.
Judicial power -- United States.
Judicial process -- United States.
Civil rights -- United States.